P Versus NP Problem - Formal Definitions For P and NP

Formal Definitions For P and NP

Conceptually a decision problem is a problem that takes as input some string w over an alphabet, and outputs "yes" or "no". If there is an algorithm (say a Turing machine, or a computer program with unbounded memory) that can produce the correct answer for any input string of length n in at most steps, where k and c are constants independent of the input string, then we say that the problem can be solved in polynomial time and we place it in the class P. Formally, P is defined as the set of all languages that can be decided by a deterministic polynomial-time Turing machine. That is,

where

and a deterministic polynomial-time Turing machine is a deterministic Turing machine M that satisfies the following two conditions:

  1. M halts on all input w and
  2. there exists such that (where O refers to the big O notation),
where
and

NP can be defined similarly using nondeterministic Turing machines (the traditional way). However, a modern approach to define NP is to use the concept of certificate and verifier. Formally, NP is defined as the set of languages over a finite alphabet that have a verifier that runs in polynomial time, where the notion of "verifier" is defined as follows.

Let L be a language over a finite alphabet, .

LNP if, and only if, there exists a binary relation and a positive integer k such that the following two conditions are satisfied:

  1. For all, such that and ; and
  2. the language over is decidable by a Turing machine in polynomial time.

A Turing machine that decides LR is called a verifier for L and a y such that is called a certificate of membership of x in L.

In general, a verifier does not have to be polynomial-time. However, for L to be in NP, there must be a verifier that runs in polynomial time.

Read more about this topic:  P Versus NP Problem

Famous quotes containing the words formal and/or definitions:

    It is in the nature of allegory, as opposed to symbolism, to beg the question of absolute reality. The allegorist avails himself of a formal correspondence between “ideas” and “things,” both of which he assumes as given; he need not inquire whether either sphere is “real” or whether, in the final analysis, reality consists in their interaction.
    Charles, Jr. Feidelson, U.S. educator, critic. Symbolism and American Literature, ch. 1, University of Chicago Press (1953)

    What I do not like about our definitions of genius is that there is in them nothing of the day of judgment, nothing of resounding through eternity and nothing of the footsteps of the Almighty.
    —G.C. (Georg Christoph)