Hall's Marriage Theorem - Proof of The Graph Theoretic Version

Proof of The Graph Theoretic Version

We first prove: If a bipartite graph G = (X + Y, E) = G(X, Y) has an X-saturating matching, then |NG(W)| ≥ |W| for all WX.

Suppose M is a matching that saturates every vertex of X. Let the set of all vertices in Y matched by M to a given W be denoted as M(W). Therefore, |M(W)|=|W|, by the definition of matching. But M(W) ⊆ NG(W), since all elements of M(W) are neighbours of W. So, |NG(W)| ≥ |M(W)| and hence, |NG(W)| ≥ |W|.

Now we prove: If |NG(W)| ≥ |W| for all W ⊆ X, then G(X,Y) has a matching that saturates every vertex in X.

Assume for contradiction that G(X,Y) is a bipartite graph that has no matching that saturates all vertices of X. Let M be a maximum matching, and u a vertex not saturated by M. Consider all augmenting paths (i.e., paths in G alternately using edges outside and inside M) starting from u. Let the set of all points in Y connected to u by these augmenting paths be T, and the set of all points in X connected to u by these augmenting paths (including u itself) be W. No maximal augmenting path can end in a vertex in Y, lest we could augment M to a strictly larger matching. Thus every vertex in T is matched by M to a vertex in W. Conversely, every vertex v in W \ {u} is matched by M to a vertex in T (namely, the vertex preceding v on an augmenting path ending at v). Thus, M provides a bijection of W \ {u} and T, which implies |W| = |T| + 1. On the other hand, NG(W) ⊆ T: let v in Y be connected to a vertex w in W. If the edge (w,v) is in M, then v is in T by the previous part of the proof, otherwise we can take an augmenting path ending in w and extend it with v, showing that v is in T. Hence, |NG(W)| = |T| = |W| − 1, a contradiction.

Read more about this topic:  Hall's Marriage Theorem

Famous quotes containing the words proof of the, proof of, proof, graph and/or version:

    If we view our children as stupid, naughty, disturbed, or guilty of their misdeeds, they will learn to behold themselves as foolish, faulty, or shameful specimens of humanity. They will regard us as judges from whom they wish to hide, and they will interpret everything we say as further proof of their unworthiness. If we view them as innocent, or at least merely ignorant, they will gain understanding from their experiences, and they will continue to regard us as wise partners.
    Polly Berrien Berends (20th century)

    There is no better proof of a man’s being truly good than his desiring to be constantly under the observation of good men.
    François, Duc De La Rochefoucauld (1613–1680)

    From whichever angle one looks at it, the application of racial theories remains a striking proof of the lowered demands of public opinion upon the purity of critical judgment.
    Johan Huizinga (1872–1945)

    In this Journal, my pen is a delicate needle point, tracing out a graph of temperament so as to show its daily fluctuations: grave and gay, up and down, lamentation and revelry, self-love and self-disgust. You get here all my thoughts and opinions, always irresponsible and often contradictory or mutually exclusive, all my moods and vapours, all the varying reactions to environment of this jelly which is I.
    W.N.P. Barbellion (1889–1919)

    It is never the thing but the version of the thing:
    The fragrance of the woman not her self,
    Her self in her manner not the solid block,
    The day in its color not perpending time,
    Time in its weather, our most sovereign lord,
    The weather in words and words in sounds of sound.
    Wallace Stevens (1879–1955)