Undecidability of Combinatorial Calculus
A normal form is any combinatory term in which the primitive combinators that occur, if any, are not applied to enough arguments to be simplified. It is undecidable whether a general combinatory term has a normal form; whether two combinatory terms are equivalent, etc. This is equivalent to the undecidability of the corresponding problems for lambda terms. However, a direct proof is as follows:
First, observe that the term
Ω = (S I I (S I I))has no normal form, because it reduces to itself after three steps, as follows:
(S I I (S I I)) = (I (S I I) (I (S I I))) = (S I I (I (S I I))) = (S I I (S I I))and clearly no other reduction order can make the expression shorter.
Now, suppose N were a combinator for detecting normal forms, such that
(N x) => T, if x has a normal form F, otherwise.(Where T and F represent the conventional Church encodings of true and false, λx.λy.x and λx.λy.y, transformed into combinatory logic. The combinatory versions have T = K and F = (K I).)
Now let
Z = (C (C (B N (S I I)) Ω) I)now consider the term (S I I Z). Does (S I I Z) have a normal form? It does if and only if the following do also:
(S I I Z) = (I Z (I Z)) = (Z (I Z)) = (Z Z) = (C (C (B N (S I I)) Ω) I Z) (definition of Z) = (C (B N (S I I)) Ω Z I) = (B N (S I I) Z Ω I) = (N (S I I Z) Ω I)Now we need to apply N to (S I I Z). Either (S I I Z) has a normal form, or it does not. If it does have a normal form, then the foregoing reduces as follows:
(N (S I I Z) Ω I) = (K Ω I) (definition of N) = Ωbut Ω does not have a normal form, so we have a contradiction. But if (S I I Z) does not have a normal form, the foregoing reduces as follows:
(N (S I I Z) Ω I) = (K I Ω I) (definition of N) = (I I) Iwhich means that the normal form of (S I I Z) is simply I, another contradiction. Therefore, the hypothetical normal-form combinator N cannot exist.
The combinatory logic analogue of Rice's theorem says that there is no complete nontrivial predicate. A predicate is a combinator that, when applied, returns either T or F. A predicate N is nontrivial if there are two arguments A and B such that NA=T and NB=F. A combinator N is complete if and only if NM has a normal form for every argument M. The analogue of Rice's theorem then says that every complete predicate is trivial. The proof of this theorem is rather simple.
Proof: By reductio ad absurdum. Suppose there is a complete non trivial predicate, say N.
Because N is supposed to be non trivial there are combinators A and B such that
(N A) = T and
(N B) = F.
Define NEGATION ≡ λx.(if (N x) then B else A) ≡ λx.((N x) B A)
Define ABSURDUM ≡ (Y NEGATION)
Fixed point theorem gives: ABSURDUM = (NEGATION ABSURDUM), for
ABSURDUM ≡ (Y NEGATION) = (NEGATION (Y NEGATION)) ≡ (NEGATION ABSURDUM).
Because N is supposed to be complete either:
- (N ABSURDUM) = F or
- (N ABSURDUM) = T
Case 1: F = (N ABSURDUM) = N (NEGATION ABSURDUM) = (N A) = T, a contradiction.
Case 2: T = (N ABSURDUM) = N (NEGATION ABSURDUM) = (N B) = F, again a contradiction.
Hence (N ABSURDUM) is neither T nor F, which contradicts the presupposition that N would be a complete non trivial predicate. QED.
From this undecidability theorem it immediately follows that there is no complete predicate that can discriminate between terms that have a normal form and terms that do not have a normal form. It also follows that there is no complete predicate, say EQUAL, such that:
(EQUAL A B) = T if A = B and
(EQUAL A B) = F if A ≠ B.
If EQUAL would exist, then for all A, λx.(EQUAL x A) would have to be a complete non trivial predicate.
Read more about this topic: Combinatory Logic
Famous quotes containing the word calculus:
“I try to make a rough music, a dance of the mind, a calculus of the emotions, a driving beat of praise out of the pain and mystery that surround me and become me. My poems are meant to make your mind get up and shout.”
—Judith Johnson Sherwin (b. 1936)