Rule of Inference - Example: Hilbert Systems For Two Propositional Logics

Example: Hilbert Systems For Two Propositional Logics

In a Hilbert system the premises and conclusion of the inference rules are simply formulas of some language, usually employing metavariables. For graphical compactness of the presentation and to emphasize the distinction between axioms and rules of inference we use the sequent notation (⊢) in this section instead of a vertical presentation of rules.

The formal language for classical propositional logic can be expressed using just negation (¬), implication (→) and propositional symbols. A well-known axiomatization, comprised of thee axiom schema and one inference rule (modus ponens) is:

(CA1) ⊢ A → (BA)
(CA2) ⊢ (A → (BC)) → ((AB) → (AC))
(CA3) ⊢ (¬A → ¬B) → (BA)
(MP) A, ABB

It may seem redundant to have two notions of inference in this case, ⊢ and →. In classical propositional logic they indeed coincide; the deduction theorem states that AB if and only if ⊢ AB. For other logics, this result does not hold however. For example, the three-valued logic Ł3 of Łukasiewicz can be axiomatized as:

(CA1) ⊢ A → (BA)
(LA2) ⊢ (AB) → ((BC) → (AC))
(CA3) ⊢ (¬A → ¬B) → (BA)
(LA4) ⊢ ((A → ¬A) → A) → A
(MP) A, ABB

This differs from classical logic by the change in axiom 2 and the addition of axiom 4. The classical deduction theorem does not hold for this logic, however a modified form does hold, namely AB if and only if ⊢ A → (AB).

Read more about this topic:  Rule Of Inference

Famous quotes containing the words systems and/or logics:

    Before anything else, we need a new age of Enlightenment. Our present political systems must relinquish their claims on truth, justice and freedom and have to replace them with the search for truth, justice, freedom and reason.
    Friedrich Dürrenmatt (1921–1990)

    When logics die,
    The secret of the soil grows through the eye,
    And blood jumps in the sun;
    Above the waste allotments the dawn halts.
    Dylan Thomas (1914–1953)