Intermediate Value Theorem - Intermediate Value Theorem and The Completeness Axiom

Intermediate Value Theorem and The Completeness Axiom

As we showed above, the Intermediate value theorem can be proved using the completeness axiom. In fact, the intermediate value theorem is equivalent to the completeness axiom; that is to say, any unbounded dense subset S of R to which the intermediate value theorem applies must also satisfy the completeness axiom.

To show this, take some bounded-above subset A of S. We will show that A has a least upper bound, using the intermediate value theorem. Consider the function f : S → defined by f(x) = 1 if x is an upper bound for A (i.e., for all sA, xs) and 0 otherwise. If A has only one element then that element is a least upper bound for A. Otherwise, there is some element a in A, and hence in S, which is not an upper bound for A. So f(a) = 0. Because A is bounded above and S is bounded, there exists bS such that b is an upper bound for S. So f(b) = 1. By the intermediate value theorem, if f is continuous then there must be some yS such that f(y) = ½. Since there is no such y, f is not continuous. So there is some point z in S such that for some ε > 0, for all δ > 0, f is not continuous at z.

f(z) cannot equal 0, though: if f(z) = 0 then z is not an upper bound for A, so any w < z is not an upper bound for A. So since f is discontinuous at z, there exists some point p in the range, for any δ > 0, such that p is an upper bound for A. But then this contradicts z not being an upper bound for A: suppose mA such that m > z. We know that there exists p with z < p < z + ½ ( m - z ) which is an upper bound for A (setting δ = ½ ( m - z ) ), so p > m. But p < z + ½ ( m - z ) < m, which is a contradiction.

So f(z) = 1, so z is an upper bound for A. Since for all v > z, v is an upper bound for A, f(v) = 1 for all v > z. Since f is not continuous at z, there there exists some point q in the range, for any δ > 0, such that q is not an upper bound for A. Now suppose there is some lS such that l < z and l is an upper bound for A. We then set δ to be ½( l - z ), so there is some r ∈ which is not an upper bound for A. But then l < z - ½ ( l - z ) < r, so l is not an upper bound for A, which is a contradiction.

So z is a least upper bound for A.

Read more about this topic:  Intermediate Value Theorem

Famous quotes containing the words intermediate, theorem, completeness and/or axiom:

    Complete courage and absolute cowardice are extremes that very few men fall into. The vast middle space contains all the intermediate kinds and degrees of courage; and these differ as much from one another as men’s faces or their humors do.
    François, Duc De La Rochefoucauld (1613–1680)

    To insure the adoration of a theorem for any length of time, faith is not enough, a police force is needed as well.
    Albert Camus (1913–1960)

    Poetry presents indivisible wholes of human consciousness, modified and ordered by the stringent requirements of form. Prose, aiming at a definite and concrete goal, generally suppresses everything inessential to its purpose; poetry, existing only to exhibit itself as an aesthetic object, aims only at completeness and perfection of form.
    Richard Harter Fogle, U.S. critic, educator. The Imagery of Keats and Shelley, ch. 1, University of North Carolina Press (1949)

    It is an axiom in political science that unless a people are educated and enlightened it is idle to expect the continuance of civil liberty or the capacity for self-government.
    Texas Declaration of Independence (March 2, 1836)